Throb
Throb
In Brief
As Stephen walks down Fleet Street in Wandering Rocks,
the hum of dynamos in the powerhouse suggests an
elemental energy pulsing in all things, including people:
"Beingless beings. Stop! Throb always without you and the
throb always within. Your heart you sing of. I between them.
Where? Between two roaring worlds where they swirl, I. Shatter
them, one and both. But stun myself too in the blow." This
metaphysical reverie was inspired at least in part by an
American novel that the young Joyce reviewed, but the
influence of that work seems limited. A richer possible source
is Arthur Schopenhauer's philosophy, which can account
both for the impression of formless energy permeating the
universe and for its connection to the energy, possibly
sexual, throbbing in Stephen.
Read More
Many annotators (Thornton, Gifford, Johnson, Slote) have
affirmed an observation made by Ellsworth Mason and Richard
Ellmann in their edition of Joyce's Critical Writings
(1959). In the 17 September 1903 Daily Express, at the
end of his short review of Kentucky writer James Lane Allen's
novel The Mettle of the Pasture (1903), Joyce quoted
"a passage of great charm" in which the hero's mother sadly
weighs his refusal to marry his fiancee as she had urged:
For her it was one of those moments when we are reminded that our lives are not in our keeping, and that whatsoever is to befall us originates in sources beyond our power. Our wills may indeed reach the length of our arms or as far as our voices can penetrate space; but without us and within moves one universe that saves us or ruins us only for its own purposes; and we are no more free amid its laws than the leaves of the forest are free to decide their own shapes and season of unfolding, to order the showers by which they are to be nourished and the storms which shall scatter them at last.
In this passage Mrs. Meredith confronts the limits of her
agency, beyond whose small reach lies a vast "universe"
that, operating both "without us and within," shapes our
destinies. As Mason and Ellmann note, there is a clear
resemblance here to the sentences in Wandering Rocks.
Like Meredith's mother, Stephen recognizes that his ego hangs
between alien worlds "without" and "within,"
and even his word "shatter" seems to recall her use of
"scatter." Joyce must have recalled Allen's conceit as he
wrote, and to the degree that Stephen can be identified with
Joyce there is verisimilitude in his thinking these thoughts
in June 1904, less than a year after the review was published.
But Joyce does something very different with the conceit.
Instead of an abstractly conceived universe that has its own
"purposes," and lays down "laws," and "saves" or "ruins"––a
kind of pantheistic version of traditional Christian
belief––the dynamos in the powerhouse give Stephen a far more
concrete and less tidy sense of what lies beyond the reach of
human senses. They are "Beingless beings," humming with
vital energy but lacking purpose, intelligibility, and even
discrete existence. Instead of a lawful universe Stephen
detects only a "Throb always without you and the throb
always within," two pulsing, swirling, "roaring
worlds" that so threaten the "I between them"
that he longs to "Shatter them, one and both." The
pessimistic urgency of his sentences bears little resemblance
to Mrs. Meredith's calm acceptance in The Mettle of the
Pasture.
Joyce could possibly have arrived at this vision on his own,
but some tracks laid down earlier in the novel encourage a
search for sources of conceptual inspiration. The last time
that readers entered the thoughts of a solitary Stephen, in Proteus,
he was using the ideas of Jacob Böhme and George
Berkeley to look for a metaphysical reality deeper than
the evidence of his senses. Might not the metaphysical
sentences in Wandering Rocks be continuing that kind
of philosophical search? Vincent Van Wyk has urged me, in
several personal communications, to consider the relevance of
Schopenhauer's Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung
(1819, reissued in a longer version in 1844), which Joyce's
contemporaries knew as The World as Will and Idea
(1883-86), a translation by Richard Burton Haldane and John
Kemp. Far more than James Lane Allen's novel, this great
philosophical work inquires into the shared reality underlying
the world "without" and the world "within." Schopenhauer
writes that "the solution of the riddle of the world is only
possible through the proper connection of outer with inner
experience" (6th ed., 1909, 3 vols., 2:20).
Schopenhauer sets himself the task of finding a way to "go
beyond the phenomenal" (1:159) to some grasp of the noumenal
reality that Kant called the Ding an sich, the
thing-in-itself. He agrees with Kant that our experience of
physical objects, existing in space and time and causally
related to one another, is only "idea" (Vorstellung),
the perceptual construct of an embodied creature. We perceive
only what our sensory and neural organs convey to
consciousness, which means that we do not perceive reality so
much as construct it: "All that in any way belongs or can
belong to the world is inevitably thus conditioned through the
subject, and exists only for the subject. The world is idea"
(1:4). Behind this "idea" (or "representation," as later
translators have rendered it), most people would assume that
some actual objects are out there. But no one can perceive
those objects as they are in themselves.
Human beings do, however, have one source of insight into the
permanently hidden reality surrounding them––not through
sensory knowledge of the world of physical objects, but by
knowing one physical object from the inside. The familiarity
that most interests Schopenhauer is not primarily cognitive.
Unlike Plato, who sought knowledge of the "Ideas" through
intellectual activities (dialectic, mystical intuition, erotic
contemplation, memory of past lives), he focuses on the "will"
that motivates human actions. Like another famous voluntarist,
Augustine, he believes that will is a more fundamental
director of human life than intellect, that it underlies all
human emotions and desires, and that it connects human beings
to the universal source of being.
But Schopenhauer, the first professed atheist in the European
philosophical tradition, does not locate this metaphysical
reality in the mind of God. He posits instead an impersonal,
"blindly acting" force that exists outside of objects, outside
space and time, outside causality, outside the duality of
knower and known. "It appears in every blind force of nature
and also in the preconsidered action of man; and the great
difference between these two is merely in the degree of the
manifestation, not in the nature of what manifests itself"
(1:143). Unlike Kant's things-in-themselves (the Table behind
the table, the Horse in the horse) this noumenal being is not
plural, but rather a single undifferentiated reality
manifested in all the things we experience. Schopenhauer named
it Will after the connection with human willing, but he might
as easily have called it Force, Energy, or Drive.
Nevertheless, the blind agency operating in all things can be felt in the deep-rooted human need to survive, and even more strongly in the need to procreate. Schopenhauer assigns more importance to sexuality (including emotions that many people would prefer to call "love") than any other philosopher before Freud: "Indeed, one may say man is concrete sexual desire; for his origin is an act of copulation and his wish of wishes is an act of copulation, and this tendency alone perpetuates and holds together his whole phenomenal existence. The will to live manifests itself indeed primarily as an effort to sustain the individual; yet this is only a step to the effort to sustain the species, and the latter endeavour must be more powerful in proportion as the life of the species surpasses that of the individual in duration, extension, and value. Therefore sexual passion is the most perfect manifestation of the will to live" (3:314). This powerful unconscious drive, which Freud came to call Id, "springs from the depths of our nature" (3:310). It is "the most vehement of desires, the wish of wishes, the concentration of all our volition" (3:314), "the ultimate goal of almost all human effort" (3:339).
It is also, Schopenhauer recognizes, the source of untold misery, frustration, confusion, conflict, and distraction, and he deplores the way important work is forever being interrupted by the "trash" that sexual desire throws up (3:339). His strong focus on sexuality and his strong ambivalence about it hold obvious relevance to Stephen Dedalus, a young man who has renounced a puritanical church without finding a way to leave behind its teachings and embraced the ideal of sexual love without finding a partner to replace prostitutes. "Your heart you sing of," Stephen thinks, but at the deepest level what impels and torments him is "the throb always within." If this throbbing urgency is indeed sexual, that appetitive drive in no way conflicts with Stephen's search for metaphysical truths. Sensory phenomena and sexual longings are windows onto the same inscrutable "Will."
Schopenhauer does not exalt will as Nietzsche does. In various ways, most notably in the realm of aesthetics, he charts paths by which human beings can lessen the grip of interested volitional striving and become disinterested observers. This aspect of his philosophy is at least roughly congruent with Stephen's wish to escape the hold of the two throbs, though Stephen gives it a far more violent expression. In a fantasy of apocalyptic destruction that he repeats in Circe with his Wagnerian cry of "Nothung!," he grandly thinks of smashing both worlds. The thought of how this universal ruin might impact the "I" in the middle deters him: "But stun myself too in the blow...Not yet awhile. A look around." He thinks of being stunned, not obliterated: apparently his belief that the Christian God would not annihilate a soul he made immortal gives him a Get Out of Will Free card.
Ca. 1900 photograph of the interior of the Dublin Corporation Electric Light station on Fleet Street. Source: esbarchives.ie.